Tuesday, 4 October 2016

Is the Trinity Still Relevant Today? (Kant)

Kant’s objection to the doctrine of the Trinity is a major factor for what Rahner claims is a marginalisation of the Trinity that has consigned Trinitarian theology to “abstract speculation”.[1] The apparent contradiction inherent to the Trinity in which three is equal to one puts the Trinity at odds with Enlightenment rationalism, this combined with Kant’s critiques buried the doctrine in Western Christianity until the neo-Orthodox advent. This essay will aim to prove that since Karl Barth, Trinitarian theology has made considerable progress in reasserting itself as a foundation of the Christian faith and, in fact, the Trinity does have relevance in the lives of the Christian community. These innovations are often framed as extensions of revelation, as they ground the Trinity in the reality of Jesus Christ.


Kant’s critiques of the Trinity are itself one in three; Kant is overall concerned that the Trinity is beyond practical reason, that the Trinity is so far removed from human conception that it bares “no practical relevance at all”.[2] Kant separates this one major criticism into three sub-reasons: first, that the Trinity is inconsolable with human rationality, “the pupil will implicitly accept one as readily as the other because he has no concept at all of a number of persons in one God”.[3] Kant’s first polemic is that there is no rational basis to talk of God as being a divisible entity. Secondly, there is no praxis to the discussion of God as a Trinity, this refers primarily to worship and ethics. Kant claims that nothing can be learned about the metaphysics of morals by coming to terms with God as Trinity, nor does a believer benefit from the distinction.[4] Kant goes on to explain that if we take a Christocentric outlook “we cannot require ourselves to rival a God”,[5] that is to say that humankind cannot use Christ as an example as this mystery is also beyond practical reason. Furthermore, Kant asserts that it would be a failing of God if God were to grant only one man universal access to moral truth, and not share it with humankind.[6] This goes to show that Kant has a fundamental misunderstanding of the Trinity as God’s self and of Jesus Christ as the Incarnate God.  Finally, Kant is suspicious of the Trinity as a means of experiencing God, as these experiences cannot be reconciled with practical reason.


Kant is however inconsistent on the issue of the Trinity; it is clear in his later work he becomes more pessimistic about what God is within the limits of practical reason. Previously he has made the claim that faith in a threefold quality is necessary to avoid a moral anthropomorphism[7] as having an incarnate deity as a figure in within the Godhead works as a mediator of God’s universal moral law. This Christological claim that Christ’s incarnation reveals the metaphysics of morality appears to directly contradict Kant’s later proposition that the Trinity is entirely without a moral praxis. One aspect that Kant remains consistent on is the expression of God’s revelation as a mystery[8] - this same conclusion is found in Barth’s Church Dogmatics. Barth acknowledges first and foremost that “God reveals Himself through Himself”, and agrees with Kant that God’s self-revelation is a true revelation of who God is, but that revelation is revealing a mystery that surpasses human conception.[9] This is itself a meaningful revelation as it places the emphasis of God’s Word back onto Christ who is a tangible reality, rather than dangerous speculation. Nonetheless both Barth and Kant acknowledge that part of self-revelation is revealing a Triune God, this very admission severely undercuts Kant’s later proposition that the Trinity is irrelevant, God is showing humanity something of God’s nature. Rahner highlights the importance of this unique position, he makes clear that God reveals a great personal truth about himself in the Trinity, as not only do humans observe the economic Trinity but also that the imminent Trinity is as God reveals it to be.[10] This in and of itself makes the Trinity infinitely valuable.

If Kant’s argument for the irrelevance of the Trinity is met seriously, the question becomes: what are the moral aspects of Trinitarian hermeneutics? Moltmann responds to this enquiry with the proposition that all Christian expressions about God have to have moral dimension in order to avoid the very problem of abstract dogmatism.[11] The core of this outlook is to be found in a Trinitarian understanding of the incarnation as this is God becoming self-complete. The Father and the Son (in two hypostases) exists “’in God’ and God in them’”,[12] not only does God then become bound to humanity through his love, the twin heresies of modalism and Arianism are avoided without retreat into a theocratic monarchy that losses its identity as Christian. Moltmann here is advocating a unique type of Divine command – which is to say that God’s command is by definition moral. However, in the context of revelation, that bares the hallmarks of a Christianised virtue ethics as Moltmann focuses solely on Jesus Christ. He claims that the Trinitarian incarnation establishes the rule of God through the incarnate Son whom is the revealer of this morality and thereby risks making Christ into a dogma. Moltmann claims it is the dichotomy of the Son’s obedience and the Father’s law that leads to the moral life.[13] Moltmann’s moral Trinitarianism is an expansion of Bonhoeffer’s ethics, Bonhoeffer is also principally concerned with not turning the reality of Christ into Christological dogmatics. He instead wants to boldly assert that there are no Christian ethics – there is only the reality of Christ.[14] Moltmann’s exegesis does however run the risk of becoming self-destructive by making virtue ethics – which is inherently dogmatic, the core of his Divine command as it centres around the incarnate Christ. It is worth noting at this point that the discussion hitherto would deeply dissatisfy Kant who would not accept any Divine command theory. Not only is it beyond his definition of practical reason but it is a direct conflict with his categorical imperative, which is itself a meta-ethical dogma.


If the Trinity is to be relevant in the lives of practicing Christians then it cannot be separated from the incarnation and the cross, the suffering Christ is a Trinitarian tragedy and therefore a uniquely Christian moment in human history. Suffering is an inescapable problem of monotheism and a principally moral challenge to God’s sovereignty. Pure monotheism points to a capricious, distant or even malevolent God, while the Triune God enters into the process of suffering as both deliverer and participant. The Son suffers the pain of death and abandonment[15] while the Father experiences the boundless grief at the death of his mortal Son.[16] The narrative of the Cross as an internal Trinitarian event rebukes Kant’s problem of relevancy as it presents a moral and experiential praxis to the issue. Grief is the epitome of the human condition; it is a shared suffering and a universal force everyone will one day will understand. The pain of dying is, likewise the epicentre of the human life along with the shared love of life, the Son dies a painful death and the Father weeps for his loss, all in the same moment. All persons of the Triune God feel the effects of suffering, so when Christians worship God they do so in a community of suffering with a God that knows all aspects of their own personal anguish - the Trinitarian hermeneutics of the tormented God are thus well within practical rationality.


In conclusion, the Trinity is only relevant within the Christian context of Revelation. The incarnation is a Trinitarian incarnation and therefore God is revealed as a Trinity. While this does not directly answer the Kant’s challenge from moral action it goes some way to addressing the confessional praxis as God’s imminence is identical with his economy which is a Triune God. This therefore means that Christian worship is a worship of Father, Son and Spirit in eternal perichoresis. The Trinity is then necessary from a Christian outlook, as Kant explains it protects God from becoming an anthropomorphic vision as claimed by Feuerbach. Furthermore, Moltmann cautions of a moral monarchy that goes together with absolute monotheism. The Trinity in meta-ethical terms can only be justified with the Cross of Christ, the death of Christ is the moment of kenosis and thereby God’s binding to humanity as a suffering Trinity. the Trinity turns Christological dogmatism into divine command and shields Christ from a regression into a merely prophetic role or a post-Kantian Arianism that has little need of Christ. These conclusions are essential to the understanding of the self-sacrifice of a loving God that does not regress to a self-destructive deity as an agent of God’s own debilitation. For God is not a law, a principle or a religion but through strictly Trinitarian means becomes a sufferer both within and without creation.

Further reading:

Barth, Karl, G. W Bromiley, and Thomas F Torrance. Church Dogmatics Volume 1: The Doctrine of the Word of God. London: T. & T. Clark International, 2004.

Bonhoeffer, Dietrich. Ethics, London: SCM press. 1955.

Kant, Immanuel. The Conflict Of The Faculties. New York, N.Y.: Abaris Books, 1979.

Kant, Immanuel, Allen W Wood, and George Di Giovanni. Religion Within The Boundaries Of Mere Reason And Other Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
Moltmann, Jürgen. The Crucified God. London: SCM Press. 2011.

Moltmann, Jürgen. Trinity and the Kingdom of God: the Doctrine of God, London; SCM Press. 1998.

Rahner, Karl. The Trinity, New York; The Crossroad Publishing Company, 2001.
Rahner, Karl. Theological Investigations: volume IV: More Recent Writings, London: Darton, Longman and Todd. 1974.
Schwöbel, Christoph. The “Renaissance of Trinitarian Theology” - revisited in Recent Developments in Trinitarian Theology: An International Symposium, Minneapolis; Ausburg Fortress Press. 2014.





[1] Schwöbel, Christoph. Trinitarian Theology Today. Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 1995. p.10
[2] Kant, Immanuel. The Conflict Of The Faculties. New York, N.Y.: Abaris Books, 1979. p. 65
[3] Ibid. p.67
[4] Ibid.
[5] Ibid.
[6] Ibid.
[7] Kant, Immanuel, Allen W Wood, and George Di Giovanni. Religion Within The Boundaries Of Mere Reason And Other Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. p. 142
[8] Ibid. p. 143
[9] Barth, Karl, G. W Bromiley, and Thomas F Torrance. Church Dogmatics Volume 1: The Doctrine of the Word of God. London: T. & T. Clark International, 2004. p.342
[10] Rahner, Karl. The Trinity, New York; The Crossroad Publishing Company, 2001. pp.101-2
[11] Moltmann, Jürgen. Trinity and the Kingdom of God: the Doctrine of God, London: SCM Press. 1998. p.62
[12] Ibid p. 121
[13] Moltmann, Jürgen. The Crucified God. London: SCM Press. 2011  p. 244
[14] Bonhoeffer, Dietrich. Ethics, London: SCM press. 1955. pp. 3-4
[15] Matthew 27:46 NRSV
[16] Moltmann, the Crucified God. P.249

No comments:

Post a Comment