Saturday, 23 June 2018

Blasphemy (Salman Rushdie and Charlie Hebdo)

This essay will discuss three prominent issues that gained potency because of both the controversy around Salmon Rushdie’s novel the Satanic Verses and; the Charlie Hebdo shooting in January 2015. Firstly, and most prominently - the extent to which society should value freedom of expression including what role ‘blasphemy’ should have both legally and culturally, and what exceptions if any should be made to protect minority groups. Secondly, how attitudes towards Islam and the Muslim community have changed and; finally, how these events have shaped western relations with the Middle East domestically and in the context of global foreign policy. This investigation will also contextualise these events within dramatic changes in politics, culture and interfaith relations between 1989 and 2015. Thus, by doing so, prove the necessity of civil liberties to protect the sovereignty of democratic nations and that a rise in Islamophobia over this twenty-five-year period has contributed greatly to the differing responses on the respective controversies.

It is worth noting some of the key differences between the two that had a direct result on the discussion following the respective events. Firstly, the content of the supposedly blasphemous works was materially and substantively different. The content of the Satanic Verses was described by the CEO of Penguin publishers – Peter Mayer as “a serious book by a serious writer.”[1] Whereas Charlie Hebdo is not by any means a scholarly body, nor does it offer much in the way of sophisticated prose. It is a satirical magazine that publishes crude and often offensive material. This difference is irrelevant in terms of the issue of free speech, as a novel by a well-respected author should have just as much protection under freedom of expression as the symbolic speech expressed by Charlie Hebdo’s cartoons. The importance of the difference in medium is that many of those involved in the Rushdie affair, especially those denouncing the book, are unlikely to have read the novel or at least not have read it in its entirety.[2] Whereas the Charlie Hebdo cartoons are more straightforward, one has simply to look at the image to understand the message being transmitted. This consequently resulted in more people being able to understand the issue rather than the abstract way in which people engaged with the Satanic Verses without the full context of the narrative, or a sophisticated understanding of Islam and blasphemy.

The second important difference between the two events is their respective cause and effect, the Rushdie affair gained infamy after the fatwa was issued by Ayatollah Khomeini in which Rushdie and his publishers were “condemned to death”.[3] Whereas the Charlie Hebdo shooting was the inverse, the violent attack appeared to be a random incident, there had been no coverage of Charlie Hebdo in the national press and the readership of the magazine was relatively small. This is an important difference, unlike the Rushdie Affair in which there was an abundance of Rushdie detractors ready to denounce the Satanic Verses; there were relatively few who were willing to speak out in defence of the Muslim community when the Charlie Hebdo cartoons were circulated in the media and online. This is likely due to the nature of the Charlie Hebdo massacre; the visceral images of cartoonists being gunned down in the street is a jarring reminder of violent extremism that could strike at the heart of western Europe as opposed to the abstract decree issued by a Mullah in a foreign country, that had little direct impact on the lives of people in Europe. Furthermore, the shooting in Paris took place in 2015, a radically different period of international relations between Europe and the Middle East, the shooting happened in the wake of the September 11th attacks, the 7/7 bombings in London and the rise of the Islamic State in Iraq and Syria (IS). This, along with outside factors such as the Iraq War and the military campaigns in the region that followed has led to a climate of fear towards Muslims and refugees from the Middle East. Consequently, an event such as the Charlie Hebdo shooting seemed to typify many of the stereotypes of the ‘barbaric’ Islamists (defined as proponents of Islam as a basis of government), who oppose Western democratic freedoms.

By far the largest issue that arose out of both controversies was surrounding the democratic principle of free speech. For the purposes of this study, free speech will be defined as the right of citizens to freely express themselves without fear of legal reprisal from the state. This includes the right to freely practice one’s religion, the right to peacefully assemble and the right to petition and protest the government. Note that this definition which has been adopted by many democratic nations worldwide grants only the protection of speech from the government, although violent reprisal from a non-state actor is just as obvious a violation of this principle. In the cases of Rushdie and Charlie Hebdo very similar discourse was used and many of the same arguments were presented. As stated above the offensive material in Satanic Verses is a complex narrative and it is not obvious why Muslims would find the book blasphemous. Ayatollah Khomeini does not give details as to why he deemed the book to be blasphemous, simply that the book was “against Islam, the Prophet of Islam, and the Qur'an”.[4] However, other prominent Muslim’s across the world have given more explicit comments on the blasphemous aspect, such as opposition Member of the Parliament of India - Syed Shahabuddin. According to him, these include: “the very title”, in Islamic mythology there is a story of the Prophet Mohammad removing two verses from the Qur’an as they had been a deception from the devil who tricked Mohammad into believing they were divine revelations from the angel Jibreel.[5] Mohammad is satirised as “Mahound” a derogatory term for Mohammed used by crusaders, the character is presented as a con-artist and the Qur’an as a forgery. Finally, Mohammad’s wives are depicted as prostitutes in a brothel delineated as the Masjid al-Haram.[6]

The chapters that sparked the controversy around the Satanic Verses are a very small part of the novel, they are also framed as a dream sequence of one of the main characters – as a fiction within a fiction. Rushdie does not attempt to make these chapters appear as a real history of Islam but rather uses the subversion of the life of Mohammad as a narrative device to describe the character’s internal struggle with cultural identity and loss of faith.[7] Despite this, Rushdie is not absolved of responsibility for the offence caused, Rushdie commented in a 1989 interview that the dream sequences start from a “historical or quasi-historical basis”.[8] Akhtar also remarks that the passages from the Satanic Verses are “too close to actual Islamic history for Rushdie’s claim to be convincing” - with respect to Rushdie arguing that his writing is a fictional work outside of a true-false dynamic. Based on Rushdie’s own personal background as an Indian-Muslim immigrant, the reader of the Satanic Verses will be aware of Rushdie’s apostasy and obvious attempt to mock a religion to which he no longer subscribes. This does not mean that Rushdie should not have written the text, nor does it mean that practising Muslims do not have the right to be offended by the text. Furthermore, this does not mean that anyone has the right to threaten, prompt or enact violence against Rushdie, the Muslim community, or anyone else exercising their right to freely express themselves. This is especially true for the Charlie Hebdo shooting, it is totally legitimate to criticise the magazine for its offensive portrayals of religious figures, especially those that belong to an already oppressed minority group – such as Muslims in France. Therefore, it is intellectually consistent to be fully supportive of Charlie Hebdo when they are attacked by terrorists (defined as violent actors in pursuit of a political goal. In this case Islamism), and to also be free to denounce them when they act reprehensibly by mocking the death of Aylan Kurdi – a six-year-old Syrian refugee.[9] As in both cases, the idea of freedom of expression is being upheld in tandem with the notion that no idea in a secular democracy is beyond criticism; it is the idea that is being supported rather than the message.

Many of the criticisms levelled against Rushdie can be found condensed into John Le Carré’s Guardian editorial from January 1990 titled: a book not worth the bloodshed. This article was published almost a year after the Ayatollah’s fatwa; consequently, Le Carré appears rather flippant about Rushdie’s current state of hiding after being bombarded with very credible death threats. He consistently places blame in the wrong place and goes far beyond reasonable boundaries to the point where he defends those who seek to commit violence against Rushdie. “you make light of the Book [the Qur’an] at your peril.”[10] This idea sets a horrific precedent, claiming that it is not the fault of those seeking to commit violence, but rather Rushdie for inciting them by offending their religious sensibilities. No other belief system is held to this height of reverence, other than religion. He continues this line of argument by defending religious fervour: “American Presidents profess to it almost as a ritual, we respect it in Christians and Jews.”[11] This is plainly a false dichotomy, never in modern history has the President of the United States asked for someone to be killed by vigilantes in the name of Christianity. If they had, it is likely they too would face a similar public criticism to what had been placed onto Ayatollah Khomeini. La Carré then continues to set up a strawman argument in which he confuses freedom of expression with being immune from criticism. There was nobody arguing that Rushdie’s Satanic Verses was above being criticised or mocked; Rushdie was not in hiding because of legitimate literary and theological disagreements, he was and is to this day under threat from Muslim zealots who want to murder him. Finally, La Carré places all the moral outrage onto Rushdie: “I could not live with the thought that by continuing to insist that my book be published, I would be inviting further bloodshed.”[12] This is tantamount to blaming Salmond Rushdie for every riot and murder that took place because of other people’s response to his work. Furthermore, it is a statement that we should not speak freely because we are afraid of how others might act violently against us – thus achieving the goal that terrorists set out. Despite the intensity of the feud between Le Carré and Rushdie at the time, it would be something Le Carré would later come to regret.[13]

The more sophisticated polemics against Rushdie come from Richard Webster and his commentary on Liberalism’s Holy War, many of these arguments fall under what Webster refers to as “authoritarian liberals”. By this, Webster makes the case that the way liberals see freedom of speech is expressed in the same sacred terms as religious zeal.[14] Before continuing with this analysis of Webster’s expanded argument, it is worth pausing to critique this initial premise. It is true that many who do not subscribe fully to a religious dogma find ideals elsewhere - in ideas of democracy, equality and justice for example. It is illegitimate to apply the same measure of unbridled devotion to those who advocate democracy and the free exchange of ideas, as those who place all their faith in a religious value system. This is because there is no epistemic distance in support for a democratic system of government, whereas religious faith requires one to suspend any other commitment to rationality. History has shown that the most equal and stable governments are democracies as they best represent the will of the citizens to live freely and prosperously rather than accepting the unaccountable decree of a religious leader or holy text. Thus, freedom of expression is held to such a high standard – it is an essential check on the power of a democratically elected government. This is significant context for the Rushdie affair, as in this instance there were calls to ban the sale of Rushdie’s book due to it causing civil unrest between different sections of the public.[15] Banning a book to maintain order gives the government the power to dictate the range of thought available to the public, or prevent authors from exposing government corruption such as when the British government attempted to ban Spycatcher - the memoirs of a former MI5 agent who exposed highly embarrassing plots by the UK special forces, such as their attempts to assassinate Egyptian president Nasser during the Suez crisis and assisting the CIA in plotting against Prime-Minister Wilson.[16]
Webster argues that there are restrictions on freedom of expression and that Rushdie is entitled and naïve to believe that he should have the right to publish the Satanic Verses with impunity. This point is not altogether unfounded, there are certain restrictions on what is considered “protected speech”, for example in the UK hate speech is not considered protected political speech under the Race Relations Act (referenced by Webster in 1990, the act has now been repealed and replaced by the 2010 Equality Act).[17] This, as well as many other pieces of legislation, prohibits language that promotes hatred based on protected characteristics such as race, gender and sexual orientation. The United States alternatively does not restrict hate speech - per the Brandenburg v. Ohio supreme court decision, a person cannot be prosecuted under the law for using inflammatory speech unless it is "directed to inciting or producing imminent lawless action and is likely to incite or produce such action".[18] This is a much more reasonable standard for the limits of free speech than what is being suggested by Webster; that the state should not have control over what types of speech are acceptable, especially in something as abstract as hate speech. After a blanket ban, one could make the case that Rushdie’s book, the fatwa issued against him, and the Charlie Hebdo cartoons be made illegal. It is almost tempting to agree that despicable speech, such as what one might hear at a Ku Klux Klan rally should be made illegal; however, giving the government power to decide what is “hateful” is dangerous for a democracy. It would be simple for the government to decide that protesters and whistle-blowers be put in jail for committing hate speech against the state. It is imperative that we be fully committed to freedom of expression, even if we do not agree with what is being said. Freedom of speech exists to protect speech that might be deemed radical or extreme. Easy speech that everyone agrees with does not need protecting. This is not to say that all speech is accepted, under the Brandenburg decision Ayatollah Khomeini’s fatwa would still be illegal, inciting violence is not protected speech.

Finally, Webster refers Rushdie back to the British common law of Blasphemous Libel (abolished 2008). He claims that the social unrest caused by Rushdie’s text would be solved by expanding the blasphemy law to include those of other faiths. Webster does this by invoking the words of Lord Scarman: “the offence belongs to a group of criminal offences designed to safeguard the internal tranquillity of the kingdom.”[19] However, the European court of Human Rights rejected an appeal to ban the Satanic Verses as “freedom of religion did not include a right not to be offended.”[20] This is the opposite of the middle eastern responses to the Satanic Verses and later the Charlie Hebdo attacks. The book was banned in several countries with high Muslim populations, including Iran, India and Saudi Arabia. Each of these nations had their own uniquely political reasons for issuing the suspension of the book. Some were in the name of peacekeeping such as India, which since its independence, has had a fierce and divisive tension between Hindus and Muslims in the subcontinent.[21] Consequently, there existed a real potential for major social unrest and violent outbursts, as allowing the publication could appear as a government endorsement of the novel. Saudi Arabia alternatively both banned the book, as well as funded campaigns across the world to have the book censored.[22] This is because Saudi Arabia is an autocratic theocracy and uses Islam as a tool to subjugate its population - a book by a Muslim apostate that can easily be framed as blasphemous gives the Sunni nation an opportunity to rally support for its existing power structures against a foreign adversary. Iran initially had very little animosity towards Rushdie or the Satanic Verses, one Iranian literary scholar claimed that the novel “distorted Islam” and “lacked artistic credentials”, but did not refer to it as blasphemous.[23] It is then likely that the fatwa was part of Khomeini’s political machinations, of which he would have any number of reasons for issuing, such as: to distract attention away from the embarrassing conclusion to the Iran-Iraq war, that left hundreds of thousands dead with very little to show for; [24] fuelling the aggression amongst Iranians for the West which had a long history of derogatory literature against Islam;[25] and to re-capture the support for the Islamic Revolution by matching the Saudi outrage against the Satanic Verses is a more public and obvious manner.[26] The issuing of the fatwa caused massive diplomatic upset in the UK, prompting all British envoys to Iran to be removed from the country.

The western response to the Rushdie affair now appears rather mild in comparison to the public and political responses to the Charlie Hebdo shootings. This is due to the differences described above as well as the rise of social media which allowed the prevalence of the twitter hashtag #JeSuisCharlie (I am Charlie). This phrase was adopted in solidarity with the victims of the shooting and a defence of the principle of free speech. There was, however, some backlash against this social movement, as the phrase is a direct endorsement of the Islamophobia expressed by the magazine, which led to the counter hashtag #JeNeSuisPasCharlie.[27] It seemed that in the condemnation of the terrorists, and the reverence paid to the martyrs at Charlie Hebdo, the Muslim community in Europe faced yet another blow to their personal identities and a further widening of social discord. This act of terrorism created a heightened sense of fear amongst those across western Europe and ironically became the vessel for more restrictive and authoritarian policies to enter the public discourse. This is best seen in the Sun’s response to the shooting in which the editors issue a full-throated support of Charlie Hebdo as well as believe that the best solution to stopping terrorism is to expand government surveillance and continue aggressive foreign policy in the Middle-East.[28] This advocacy for a heightened surveillance state is a far greater threat to civil liberties than terrorism; government spying is an indirect assault on freedom of expression as it passively influences who citizens contact, where they congregate and the activities that they participate in for fear that they may be branded a ‘person of interest’. While terrorist acts are terrifying and shocking, they are also infrequent and should not be used by government security agencies to turn the entire population into potential suspects; or limit what is considered acceptable political speech, as was attempted in France less than a year after the Charlie Hebdo massacre.[29]

In conclusion, both controversies had large scale impacts on the discussion regarding freedom of expression and the western cultural view of Muslims and blasphemy. Very few issues are successful in animating the population to defend civil liberties in the way that these events have prompted a heightened awareness for freedom of expression. To assume that the extent of the outrage was not in large part the result of Islamophobia would be enormously naïve. despite this, the conversation regarding the limits of free speech are hugely necessary and it is vital that this essential democratic right is protected, even if the discussion assists in normalising bigotry. This is because the freedom to express dissatisfaction with the state is the primary defence of the rest of our rights as citizens, which cannot be abridged regardless of the cost. These events led many to conclude that the idea of blasphemy is an outdated concept belonging to a more uncivilised period of human history, sometimes seen in oppressive autocracies in the Middle East, which has led to the perception of a large cultural divide between Islam and the West. These events furthered the belief amongst Muslims that people outside their own communities would support any form of denigration towards the Prophet Mohammad or the Qur’an, leading to a rise in animosity and a decline in community cohesion. It is unclear what further consequences the Charlie Hebdo attack will have on the cultural zeitgeist due to the recentness of the event, however it can be reasonably inferred that this case study will remain prevalent to discussions regarding Islam, freedom of expression and Middle-East policy just as the Rushdie affair did – as both cases are a perfect storm of conflicting ideologies and cultural divergence.

Bibliography
Akhtar, Shabbir. Be Careful With Muhammad!. London: Bellew, 1989.
Brooks, David (2015). ‘I am Not Charlie’. New York Times 8th Jan.   http://www.nytimes.com/2015/01/09/opinion/david-brooks-i-am-not-charlie-hebdo.html?_r=1 retrieved 01/01/2017
Bulloch, John and Morris, Harvey. The Gulf War: Its Origins, History and Consequences. London: Methuen Publishing Ltd, 1989.
Greenwald, Glen (2016). ‘Where Were the Post-Hebdo Free Speech Crusaders as France Spent the Last Year Crushing Free Speech?’ The Intercept 8th Jan.  https://theintercept.com/2016/01/08/where-were-the-post-hebdo-free-speech-crusaders-as-france-spent-the-last-year-crushing-free-speech/ Retrieved 05/01/2017
Hawting, G.R. The Idea of Idolatry and the Emergence of Islam: From Polemic to History, Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
Isa Patel, Ismail. Mis/Representations of Islam: Reading Salman Rushdie's The Satanic Verses, London 1998 https://www.scribd.com/document/107049639/Mis-Representations-of-Islam-Reading-Salman-Rushdie-s-The-Satanic-Verses-By-Ismail-Isa-Patel-London-1998accessed retrieved 02/01/2017
Le Carré, John (1990). ‘A Book Not Worth the Bloodshed’. the Guardian, 15th Jan.
Malik, Kenan. From Fatwa to Jihad. 1st ed. Brooklyn, NY: Melville House Pub., 2009.
Parker, Richard A. (2003). "Brandenburg v. Ohio". In Parker, Richard A. (ed.) Free Speech on Trial: Communication Perspectives on Landmark Supreme Court Decisions. Tuscaloosa, AL: University of Alabama Press.
Ruthven, Malise. A Satanic Affair. 1st ed. London: Chatto & Windus, 1990.
The Telegraph (2012) ‘Le Carré regrets Rushdie fatwa feud’. 12th Nov.  http://www.telegraph.co.uk/culture/books/booknews/9671959/Le-Carre-regrets-Rushdie-fatwa-feud.html retrieved 01/01/2017
The Sun (2015), ‘Freedom Fight’ 9th Jan. https://www.thesun.co.uk/archives/news/7504/freedom-fight/ retrieved 01/01/2017
Webster, Richard. A Brief History of Blasphemy. Southwold: Orwell Pr., 1990.







[1] Malik, Kenan. From Fatwa to Jihad. 1st ed. Brooklyn, NY: Melville House Pub., 2009. p.11
[2] Ibid. p.2
[4] Ibid.
[5] Hawting, G.R. The Idea of Idolatry and the Emergence of Islam: From Polemic to History, Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press, 1999. pp.130-6
[6] Malik, From Fatwa to Jihad. p.2-3
[7] Ruthven, Malise. A Satanic Affair. 1st ed. London: Chatto & Windus, 1990. p.27
[8] Akhtar, Shabbir. Be Careful With Muhammad!. London: Bellew, 1989. p.129
[9] BBC (2016) 13th Jan. http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/world-europe-35306906 retrieved 01/01/2017
[10] Le Carré, John. A Book Not Worth the Bloodshed, the Guardian, 15th Jan. 1990
[11] Ibid.
[12] Ibid.
[13] The Telegraph (2012). ‘Le Carré regrets Rushdie fatwa’ feud 12th Nov. http://www.telegraph.co.uk/culture/books/booknews/9671959/Le-Carre-regrets-Rushdie-fatwa-feud.html retrieved 01/01/2017
[14] Webster, Richard. A Brief History of Blasphemy. Southwold: Orwell Pr., 1990. p.60
[15] Le Carré “Withdraw his [Rushdie] book until a calmer time has come.”
[16]  "Observer and Guardian v. The United Kingdom". European Court of Human Rights. Section II. A. Point 14: Subsection a-e. http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng#{"dmdocnumber":["695582"],"itemid":["001-57705"]} Retrieved 01/01/2017
[17] Webster, Blasphemy. p.45.
[18] Parker, Richard A. (2003). "Brandenburg v. Ohio". In Parker, Richard A. (ed.). Free Speech on Trial: Communication Perspectives on Landmark Supreme Court Decisions. Tuscaloosa, AL: University of Alabama Press. pp. 145–159.
[19] Webster, Blasphemy. p.65
[21] Malik, From Fatwa to Jihad p.3
[22] Ibid. p.6
[23] Ibid.
[24] Bulloch, John and Morris, Harvey. The Gulf War: Its Origins, History and Consequences. London: Methuen Publishing Ltd, 1989. p.xvi
[25] Isa Patel, Ismail. Mis/Representations of Islam: Reading Salman Rushdie's The Satanic Verses, London 1998 https://www.scribd.com/document/107049639/Mis-Representations-of-Islam-Reading-Salman-Rushdie-s-The-Satanic-Verses-By-Ismail-Isa-Patel-London-1998 retrieved 02/01/2017
[26] Pipes, Daniel. The Rushdie Affair: The Novel, the Ayatollah, and the West. New York, NY: Carol Pub. Group, 1990. p.133-4
[27] Brooks, David. I am Not Charlie. New York Times 8th Jan. 2015  http://www.nytimes.com/2015/01/09/opinion/david-brooks-i-am-not-charlie-hebdo.html?_r=1 retrieved 01/01/2017
[28] The Sun (2015), ‘Freedom Fight’ 9th Jan. https://www.thesun.co.uk/archives/news/7504/freedom-fight/ retrieved 01/01/2017.
[29] Greenwald, Glen (2016). ‘Where Were the Post-Hebdo Free Speech Crusaders as France Spent the Last Year Crushing Free Speech?’ The Intercept 8th Jan.  https://theintercept.com/2016/01/08/where-were-the-post-hebdo-free-speech-crusaders-as-france-spent-the-last-year-crushing-free-speech/ Retrieved 05/01/2017

Tuesday, 4 October 2016

Is the Trinity Still Relevant Today? (Kant)

Kant’s objection to the doctrine of the Trinity is a major factor for what Rahner claims is a marginalisation of the Trinity that has consigned Trinitarian theology to “abstract speculation”.[1] The apparent contradiction inherent to the Trinity in which three is equal to one puts the Trinity at odds with Enlightenment rationalism, this combined with Kant’s critiques buried the doctrine in Western Christianity until the neo-Orthodox advent. This essay will aim to prove that since Karl Barth, Trinitarian theology has made considerable progress in reasserting itself as a foundation of the Christian faith and, in fact, the Trinity does have relevance in the lives of the Christian community. These innovations are often framed as extensions of revelation, as they ground the Trinity in the reality of Jesus Christ.


Kant’s critiques of the Trinity are itself one in three; Kant is overall concerned that the Trinity is beyond practical reason, that the Trinity is so far removed from human conception that it bares “no practical relevance at all”.[2] Kant separates this one major criticism into three sub-reasons: first, that the Trinity is inconsolable with human rationality, “the pupil will implicitly accept one as readily as the other because he has no concept at all of a number of persons in one God”.[3] Kant’s first polemic is that there is no rational basis to talk of God as being a divisible entity. Secondly, there is no praxis to the discussion of God as a Trinity, this refers primarily to worship and ethics. Kant claims that nothing can be learned about the metaphysics of morals by coming to terms with God as Trinity, nor does a believer benefit from the distinction.[4] Kant goes on to explain that if we take a Christocentric outlook “we cannot require ourselves to rival a God”,[5] that is to say that humankind cannot use Christ as an example as this mystery is also beyond practical reason. Furthermore, Kant asserts that it would be a failing of God if God were to grant only one man universal access to moral truth, and not share it with humankind.[6] This goes to show that Kant has a fundamental misunderstanding of the Trinity as God’s self and of Jesus Christ as the Incarnate God.  Finally, Kant is suspicious of the Trinity as a means of experiencing God, as these experiences cannot be reconciled with practical reason.


Kant is however inconsistent on the issue of the Trinity; it is clear in his later work he becomes more pessimistic about what God is within the limits of practical reason. Previously he has made the claim that faith in a threefold quality is necessary to avoid a moral anthropomorphism[7] as having an incarnate deity as a figure in within the Godhead works as a mediator of God’s universal moral law. This Christological claim that Christ’s incarnation reveals the metaphysics of morality appears to directly contradict Kant’s later proposition that the Trinity is entirely without a moral praxis. One aspect that Kant remains consistent on is the expression of God’s revelation as a mystery[8] - this same conclusion is found in Barth’s Church Dogmatics. Barth acknowledges first and foremost that “God reveals Himself through Himself”, and agrees with Kant that God’s self-revelation is a true revelation of who God is, but that revelation is revealing a mystery that surpasses human conception.[9] This is itself a meaningful revelation as it places the emphasis of God’s Word back onto Christ who is a tangible reality, rather than dangerous speculation. Nonetheless both Barth and Kant acknowledge that part of self-revelation is revealing a Triune God, this very admission severely undercuts Kant’s later proposition that the Trinity is irrelevant, God is showing humanity something of God’s nature. Rahner highlights the importance of this unique position, he makes clear that God reveals a great personal truth about himself in the Trinity, as not only do humans observe the economic Trinity but also that the imminent Trinity is as God reveals it to be.[10] This in and of itself makes the Trinity infinitely valuable.

If Kant’s argument for the irrelevance of the Trinity is met seriously, the question becomes: what are the moral aspects of Trinitarian hermeneutics? Moltmann responds to this enquiry with the proposition that all Christian expressions about God have to have moral dimension in order to avoid the very problem of abstract dogmatism.[11] The core of this outlook is to be found in a Trinitarian understanding of the incarnation as this is God becoming self-complete. The Father and the Son (in two hypostases) exists “’in God’ and God in them’”,[12] not only does God then become bound to humanity through his love, the twin heresies of modalism and Arianism are avoided without retreat into a theocratic monarchy that losses its identity as Christian. Moltmann here is advocating a unique type of Divine command – which is to say that God’s command is by definition moral. However, in the context of revelation, that bares the hallmarks of a Christianised virtue ethics as Moltmann focuses solely on Jesus Christ. He claims that the Trinitarian incarnation establishes the rule of God through the incarnate Son whom is the revealer of this morality and thereby risks making Christ into a dogma. Moltmann claims it is the dichotomy of the Son’s obedience and the Father’s law that leads to the moral life.[13] Moltmann’s moral Trinitarianism is an expansion of Bonhoeffer’s ethics, Bonhoeffer is also principally concerned with not turning the reality of Christ into Christological dogmatics. He instead wants to boldly assert that there are no Christian ethics – there is only the reality of Christ.[14] Moltmann’s exegesis does however run the risk of becoming self-destructive by making virtue ethics – which is inherently dogmatic, the core of his Divine command as it centres around the incarnate Christ. It is worth noting at this point that the discussion hitherto would deeply dissatisfy Kant who would not accept any Divine command theory. Not only is it beyond his definition of practical reason but it is a direct conflict with his categorical imperative, which is itself a meta-ethical dogma.


If the Trinity is to be relevant in the lives of practicing Christians then it cannot be separated from the incarnation and the cross, the suffering Christ is a Trinitarian tragedy and therefore a uniquely Christian moment in human history. Suffering is an inescapable problem of monotheism and a principally moral challenge to God’s sovereignty. Pure monotheism points to a capricious, distant or even malevolent God, while the Triune God enters into the process of suffering as both deliverer and participant. The Son suffers the pain of death and abandonment[15] while the Father experiences the boundless grief at the death of his mortal Son.[16] The narrative of the Cross as an internal Trinitarian event rebukes Kant’s problem of relevancy as it presents a moral and experiential praxis to the issue. Grief is the epitome of the human condition; it is a shared suffering and a universal force everyone will one day will understand. The pain of dying is, likewise the epicentre of the human life along with the shared love of life, the Son dies a painful death and the Father weeps for his loss, all in the same moment. All persons of the Triune God feel the effects of suffering, so when Christians worship God they do so in a community of suffering with a God that knows all aspects of their own personal anguish - the Trinitarian hermeneutics of the tormented God are thus well within practical rationality.


In conclusion, the Trinity is only relevant within the Christian context of Revelation. The incarnation is a Trinitarian incarnation and therefore God is revealed as a Trinity. While this does not directly answer the Kant’s challenge from moral action it goes some way to addressing the confessional praxis as God’s imminence is identical with his economy which is a Triune God. This therefore means that Christian worship is a worship of Father, Son and Spirit in eternal perichoresis. The Trinity is then necessary from a Christian outlook, as Kant explains it protects God from becoming an anthropomorphic vision as claimed by Feuerbach. Furthermore, Moltmann cautions of a moral monarchy that goes together with absolute monotheism. The Trinity in meta-ethical terms can only be justified with the Cross of Christ, the death of Christ is the moment of kenosis and thereby God’s binding to humanity as a suffering Trinity. the Trinity turns Christological dogmatism into divine command and shields Christ from a regression into a merely prophetic role or a post-Kantian Arianism that has little need of Christ. These conclusions are essential to the understanding of the self-sacrifice of a loving God that does not regress to a self-destructive deity as an agent of God’s own debilitation. For God is not a law, a principle or a religion but through strictly Trinitarian means becomes a sufferer both within and without creation.

Further reading:

Barth, Karl, G. W Bromiley, and Thomas F Torrance. Church Dogmatics Volume 1: The Doctrine of the Word of God. London: T. & T. Clark International, 2004.

Bonhoeffer, Dietrich. Ethics, London: SCM press. 1955.

Kant, Immanuel. The Conflict Of The Faculties. New York, N.Y.: Abaris Books, 1979.

Kant, Immanuel, Allen W Wood, and George Di Giovanni. Religion Within The Boundaries Of Mere Reason And Other Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
Moltmann, Jürgen. The Crucified God. London: SCM Press. 2011.

Moltmann, Jürgen. Trinity and the Kingdom of God: the Doctrine of God, London; SCM Press. 1998.

Rahner, Karl. The Trinity, New York; The Crossroad Publishing Company, 2001.
Rahner, Karl. Theological Investigations: volume IV: More Recent Writings, London: Darton, Longman and Todd. 1974.
Schwöbel, Christoph. The “Renaissance of Trinitarian Theology” - revisited in Recent Developments in Trinitarian Theology: An International Symposium, Minneapolis; Ausburg Fortress Press. 2014.





[1] Schwöbel, Christoph. Trinitarian Theology Today. Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 1995. p.10
[2] Kant, Immanuel. The Conflict Of The Faculties. New York, N.Y.: Abaris Books, 1979. p. 65
[3] Ibid. p.67
[4] Ibid.
[5] Ibid.
[6] Ibid.
[7] Kant, Immanuel, Allen W Wood, and George Di Giovanni. Religion Within The Boundaries Of Mere Reason And Other Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. p. 142
[8] Ibid. p. 143
[9] Barth, Karl, G. W Bromiley, and Thomas F Torrance. Church Dogmatics Volume 1: The Doctrine of the Word of God. London: T. & T. Clark International, 2004. p.342
[10] Rahner, Karl. The Trinity, New York; The Crossroad Publishing Company, 2001. pp.101-2
[11] Moltmann, Jürgen. Trinity and the Kingdom of God: the Doctrine of God, London: SCM Press. 1998. p.62
[12] Ibid p. 121
[13] Moltmann, Jürgen. The Crucified God. London: SCM Press. 2011  p. 244
[14] Bonhoeffer, Dietrich. Ethics, London: SCM press. 1955. pp. 3-4
[15] Matthew 27:46 NRSV
[16] Moltmann, the Crucified God. P.249

Wednesday, 9 September 2015

A Rebuttal Against Capital Punishment

The death penalty has been a controversial topic throughout the western world for decades, with current Minister for Justice in the UK, Michael Gove in favour of re-introducing the practice in Great Britain according to his 1998 article in The Times[1], as well as numerous surveys that indicate that a majority of American’s support capital punishment[2] despite their acknowledgment that innocent people may die as a result. This article will aim to address and comment on both the philosophical and pragmatic justifications and criticisms of capital punishment and assess the role of the sentence within 21st century justice.

Reciprocal punishment: the most popular defense for capital punishment is “an eye for an eye”, but as Gandhi claimed “an eye for an eye makes the whole world blind”. It is an indication of a warped culture in which the government has made itself an agent of revenge; no responsible government should be involved in the murder of its own citizens. The death penalty arises from humankind's barbaric past and to make the claim that ‘murder is the answer to murder’ debases the society through savagery and blatant hypocrisy. Furthermore if a life pays for a life, then rape pays for rape, arson pays for arson – this measure of punishment once again proves that by murdering a murderer, we who adjudicate and enable that punishment are no better than those we are condemning of the deepest depravity. 

“What would you do?”: The trump card for capital punishment advocates, “what would you do if it were your mother, brothers and sons?” When placed at the centre of such a proposition it is all too easy to lose one’s mind to an ugly and uncivilised position. However this is not how justice should be carried out, the victims do not choose the punishment and justice is dispensed by an impartial peer group. Look back only to the lynchings that terrorised African Americans for centuries to see how prejudices and biases can prompt the most depraved acts of mass insanity.[3]

“They deserve it.”: Similar to the “eye for an eye” argument, this justification arises out of a feeling that justice would be served if a killer were killed, in this case, such an execution should be performed in the town square – where all can see ‘justice’ in action. If one must avert their eyes at a sight that is too gruesome and gratuitous for all members of society to participate in, then justice is not taking place. Islamic State supporters do not turn their heads at the beheadings of infidels or the falling of homosexuals[4] and we condemn them as “barbarians”, while the US conducts its executions in dark corners and windowless rooms then calls it “Justice”.

In April 2014 Clayton Lockett: convicted of murder in 2000, was given a lethal injection - the untested concoction resulted in Lockett suffering a forty three minute long execution until he eventually died of a heart attack. The White House later released a statement claiming that this execution “fell short of humane standards”[5]. Clayton Locket however was not an isolated incident, between 1890 and 2010 there have been 273 botched executions in the United States[6], this statistic alone shows the deeply fissured morality of capital punishment as nearly 300 people have been tortured to death by the mismanagement of the practice. There are certainly those that would make the argument that we should not concern ourselves with the suffering endured by vicious killers like Clayton Lockett - including Senator James Inhofe (R-OK) who made the following statement: “The people who’re concerned about how much he must have suffered, they ought to think about how much she [Lockett’s victim] suffered, and I don’t think that should change anything.”[7] By having this execution go so terribly wrong the State of Oklahoma has created unnecessary sympathy for Lockett, a man that raped, shot and buried a 19 year old woman alive. No-one disputes that Lockett was a wicked person who performed a wicked act, however no crime can in good conscience be punishable by execution through torture, if Lockett had received a life imprisonment, there would be no ambivalence and Clayton Lockett would go down in history as the brutal killer that he was, rather than the man that was butchered by the State. The eight amendment to the United States Constitution specifically prohibits “cruel and unusual punishment” and thus every botched execution is a counter-narrative to the values and principles of American democracy.

Deterrence: Deterrence in and of itself is a deeply illogical mode of handing down punishments, in Great Britain for example, the death penalty could be appointed for crimes as minor as shoplifting or stealing livestock[8]. This imparted the message that people were not being sentenced for stealing but rather, that things may not be stolen. Kant would certainly argue that using a human being to teach society a lesson is universally immoral as it takes a person as no more than a means to an end. The added layer of absurdity is capital punishments universal application for minor offences, which is fundamentally ironic as rather than deterring a criminal caught stealing, it prompts murder as a necessity due to the criminal having already forfeited their life. Furthermore in many cases a prosecution arguing for the death penalty does not lead to a just outcome as those on trial will be more focused on negating the ultimate punishment and accept a plea deal for a crime they may not have committed, they see escaping with their lives as enough of a victory that they capitulate their freedom - Once again showing the death penalty is an infection upon justice.

Recidivism: Proponents of the death penalty will often site that execution is the best way to ensure that someone never repeats their heinous crime. While this is undeniably true, it is only proof that extreme solutions produce extreme outcomes; the Iraq war would have been won quicker by using a nuclear weapon on Saddam’s palace - that is also undeniable. A responsible society should act pro-rata in matters of paramount significance such as warfare and due process. Moreover what extra thing is achieved by executing a criminal that isn’t already achieved through life in prison, other than indulging our vitriol with a superfluous act of violence? The goal of a righteous justice system is to rehabilitate its criminal population, the death penalty in this way is always a moral and philosophical failure as it is an intrinsic admission of failure: ‘I could not save you, and thus I must end you.’


Cost effectiveness: According to research conducted by Gallup in 1991 there was virtually no-one arguing that the death penalty saved taxpayer money, this rate has risen by 15% in 2014, and is the only reason listed on the study that consistently rose in support[9]. The great irony of this is that capital punishment is definitively more costly to the state than life imprisonment. The Associated Press investigation found “It's 10 times more expensive to kill them than to keep them alive.” According to a California Justice[10]. There are many factors that lead to this spike in costs, mostly it is due to the inflated price of attorneys and the numerous stages of appeals that the state goes through before reaching a final verdict. In any case, frugality is not a legitimate reason to end someone’s life, a human being is an irreplaceable work of art, their life is rare, beautiful and miraculous – no amount of money can compensate for it.

Innocence: The justice system as it currently stands is unquestionably flawed, jurors have biases and feel outside influences, prosecutors hide evidence and judges often dispense unnecessary sentences, so how can we justify handing down the ultimate punishment when the way justice is conducted is so corrupt? A study was conducted by the National Academy of Sciences (PNAS) that examined the exoneration rate of prisoners on death row and attempted to calculate the margin of error; the study found that a conservative estimate of 4% of those whom had been given the death penalty were innocent[11]. The results showed that of the 7,482 people put on death row between 1973 and 2004, 117 were exonerated while on death row with the study claiming the actual number to be up to 340. In lieu of all other arguments put forward throughout the discussion on capital punishment, perhaps there is some metaphysical reason that necessitates capital punishment, but can anyone really justify living under a system that has a clear conscience after murdering an innocent person? Can society have become so morally bankrupt that we accept the deaths of innocent people as merely errors in an otherwise righteous prosecution?

The Crucified God: Jesus Christ, likely the most famous recipient of the death penalty, a man whom was tortured and murdered for committing sedition, a crime that is still punishable by death in many nations across the world. Christ’s death at the hands of the Roman occupiers is the foundation of a religion that centres on peace and love. To support the death penalty is to stand with the oppressors, those whom condemned Jesus to suffer and die at Golgotha. “You have heard that it was said, ‘Eye for eye, and tooth for tooth’. But I tell you, do not resist an evil person. If anyone slaps you on the right cheek, turn to them the other cheek also.” (Matthew 5:38-9) Jesus is directly challenging the Laws of the Old Testament, furthermore, Jesus puts this into practice – an adulterous woman is to pay the ultimate price for her transgression and Jesus asks “Let anyone among you who is without sin be the first to throw a stone.” (John 8:7) Here Jesus again refutes the excessive legalism of 1st century Judaism and re-establishes the value of human life.

The death penalty pollutes the justice system with the ugliest and inhumane form of punishment that corrodes the moral foundation of any society that practices it, notwithstanding flawed due process and the systematic corruption from prosecution as well as racial biases that disproportionately affect minority groups and other jury prejudices. 
However Christians have an inherent duty as followers of Christ to fight against the death penalty wherever it exists.

“Many that live deserve death. And some that die deserve life. Can you give it to them? Then do not be too eager to deal out death in judgement.” - J.R.R Tolkien (Lord of the Rings) 






[1] http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/politics/conservative/11595776/Michael-Gove-new-Justice-Secretary-wanted-to-bring-back-hanging.html
[2] http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/post-nation/wp/2015/04/17/most-americans-support-the-death-penalty-they-also-agree-that-an-innocent-person-might-get-put-to-death/
[5] http://www.theguardian.com/world/2014/apr/30/oklahoma-clayton-lockett-botched-execution-explanation
[6] http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/magazine-28555978
[7] http://talkingpointsmemo.com/livewire/james-inhofe-oklahoma-clayton-lockett-execution
[8] http://www.capitalpunishmentuk.org/timeline.html
[9] http://www.vox.com/xpress/2014/11/13/7214117/capital-punishment-polls
[10] http://www.nbcnews.com/id/29552692/ns/us_news-crime_and_courts/t/execute-or-not-question-cost/#.VeS4DPZVhBe
[11] http://www.forbes.com/sites/elizabethlopatto/2014/04/29/how-many-innocent-people-are-sentenced-to-death/